Gödel's Constructible Universe
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In mathematics, in
set theory Set theory is the branch of mathematical logic that studies sets, which can be informally described as collections of objects. Although objects of any kind can be collected into a set, set theory, as a branch of mathematics, is mostly conce ...
, the constructible universe (or Gödel's constructible universe), denoted by , is a particular class of sets that can be described entirely in terms of simpler sets. is the union of the constructible hierarchy . It was introduced by Kurt Gödel in his 1938 paper "The Consistency of the Axiom of Choice and of the Generalized Continuum-Hypothesis". In this paper, he proved that the constructible universe is an inner model of ZF set theory (that is, of
Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory In set theory, Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, named after mathematicians Ernst Zermelo and Abraham Fraenkel, is an axiomatic system that was proposed in the early twentieth century in order to formulate a theory of sets free of paradoxes such ...
with the
axiom of choice In mathematics, the axiom of choice, or AC, is an axiom of set theory equivalent to the statement that ''a Cartesian product of a collection of non-empty sets is non-empty''. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection ...
excluded), and also that the axiom of choice and the
generalized continuum hypothesis In mathematics, the continuum hypothesis (abbreviated CH) is a hypothesis about the possible sizes of infinite sets. It states that or equivalently, that In Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice (ZFC), this is equivalent to ...
are true in the constructible universe. This shows that both propositions are
consistent In classical deductive logic, a consistent theory is one that does not lead to a logical contradiction. The lack of contradiction can be defined in either semantic or syntactic terms. The semantic definition states that a theory is consistent ...
with the basic axioms of set theory, if ZF itself is consistent. Since many other theorems only hold in systems in which one or both of the propositions is true, their consistency is an important result.


What is

can be thought of as being built in "stages" resembling the construction of
von Neumann universe In set theory and related branches of mathematics, the von Neumann universe, or von Neumann hierarchy of sets, denoted by ''V'', is the class of hereditary well-founded sets. This collection, which is formalized by Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory (ZF ...
, . The stages are indexed by ordinals. In von Neumann's universe, at a
successor Successor may refer to: * An entity that comes after another (see Succession (disambiguation)) Film and TV * ''The Successor'' (film), a 1996 film including Laura Girling * ''The Successor'' (TV program), a 2007 Israeli television program Musi ...
stage, one takes to be the set of ''all'' subsets of the previous stage, . By contrast, in Gödel's constructible universe , one uses ''only'' those subsets of the previous stage that are: *definable by a formula in the
formal language In logic, mathematics, computer science, and linguistics, a formal language consists of words whose letters are taken from an alphabet and are well-formed according to a specific set of rules. The alphabet of a formal language consists of sy ...
of set theory, *with
parameters A parameter (), generally, is any characteristic that can help in defining or classifying a particular system (meaning an event, project, object, situation, etc.). That is, a parameter is an element of a system that is useful, or critical, when ...
from the previous stage and, *with the quantifiers interpreted to range over the previous stage. By limiting oneself to sets defined only in terms of what has already been constructed, one ensures that the resulting sets will be constructed in a way that is independent of the peculiarities of the surrounding model of set theory and contained in any such model. Define L is defined by
transfinite recursion Transfinite induction is an extension of mathematical induction to well-ordered sets, for example to sets of ordinal numbers or cardinal numbers. Its correctness is a theorem of ZFC. Induction by cases Let P(\alpha) be a property defined for a ...
as follows: * L_ := \varnothing. * L_ := \operatorname(L_\alpha). * If \lambda is a
limit ordinal In set theory, a limit ordinal is an ordinal number that is neither zero nor a successor ordinal. Alternatively, an ordinal λ is a limit ordinal if there is an ordinal less than λ, and whenever β is an ordinal less than λ, then there exists a ...
, then L_ := \bigcup_ L_. Here < means precedes . * L := \bigcup_ L_. Here Ord denotes the class of all ordinals. If is an element of , then = ∈ Def () = . So is a subset of , which is a subset of the
power set In mathematics, the power set (or powerset) of a set is the set of all subsets of , including the empty set and itself. In axiomatic set theory (as developed, for example, in the ZFC axioms), the existence of the power set of any set is post ...
of . Consequently, this is a tower of nested
transitive set In set theory, a branch of mathematics, a set A is called transitive if either of the following equivalent conditions hold: * whenever x \in A, and y \in x, then y \in A. * whenever x \in A, and x is not an urelement, then x is a subset of A. Simil ...
s. But itself is a proper class. The elements of are called "constructible" sets; and itself is the "constructible universe". The "
axiom of constructibility The axiom of constructibility is a possible axiom for set theory in mathematics that asserts that every set is constructible. The axiom is usually written as ''V'' = ''L'', where ''V'' and ''L'' denote the von Neumann universe and the construc ...
", aka " = ", says that every set (of ) is constructible, i.e. in .


Additional facts about the sets

An equivalent definition for is: For any finite ordinal , the sets and are the same (whether equals or not), and thus = : their elements are exactly the
hereditarily finite set In mathematics and set theory, hereditarily finite sets are defined as finite sets whose elements are all hereditarily finite sets. In other words, the set itself is finite, and all of its elements are finite sets, recursively all the way down to t ...
s. Equality beyond this point does not hold. Even in models of ZFC in which equals , is a proper subset of , and thereafter is a proper subset of the power set of for all > . On the other hand, = does imply that equals if = , for example if is inaccessible. More generally, = implies = for all infinite cardinals . If is an infinite ordinal then there is a bijection between and , and the bijection is constructible. So these sets are
equinumerous In mathematics, two sets or classes ''A'' and ''B'' are equinumerous if there exists a one-to-one correspondence (or bijection) between them, that is, if there exists a function from ''A'' to ''B'' such that for every element ''y'' of ''B'', the ...
in any model of set theory that includes them. As defined above, Def() is the set of subsets of defined by Δ formulas (with respect to the Levy hierarchy, i.e., formulas of set theory containing only bounded quantifiers) that use as parameters only and its elements. Another definition, due to Gödel, characterizes each as the intersection of the power set of with the closure of L_\alpha\cup\ under a collection of nine explicit functions, similar to Gödel operations. This definition makes no reference to definability. All arithmetical subsets of and relations on belong to (because the arithmetic definition gives one in ). Conversely, any subset of belonging to is arithmetical (because elements of can be coded by natural numbers in such a way that ∈ is definable, i.e., arithmetic). On the other hand, already contains certain non-arithmetical subsets of , such as the set of (natural numbers coding) true arithmetical statements (this can be defined from so it is in ). All hyperarithmetical subsets of and relations on belong to L_ (where \omega_1^ stands for the
Church–Kleene ordinal In mathematics, particularly set theory, non-recursive ordinals are large countable ordinals greater than all the recursive ordinals, and therefore can not be expressed using ordinal collapsing functions. The Church–Kleene ordinal and varian ...
), and conversely any subset of that belongs to L_ is hyperarithmetical.Barwise 1975, page 60 (comment following proof of theorem 5.9)


is a standard inner model of ZFC

is a standard model, i.e. it is a transitive class and it uses the real element relationship, so it is well-founded. is an inner model, i.e. it contains all the ordinal numbers of and it has no "extra" sets beyond those in , but it might be a proper subclass of . is a model of ZFC, which means that it satisfies the following axioms: *
Axiom of regularity In mathematics, the axiom of regularity (also known as the axiom of foundation) is an axiom of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory that states that every non-empty set ''A'' contains an element that is disjoint from ''A''. In first-order logic, the ...
: Every non-empty set contains some element such that and are disjoint sets. : (,∈) is a substructure of (,∈), which is well founded, so is well founded. In particular, if ∈ ∈ , then by the transitivity of , ∈ . If we use this same as in , then it is still disjoint from because we are using the same element relation and no new sets were added. *
Axiom of extensionality In axiomatic set theory and the branches of logic, mathematics, and computer science that use it, the axiom of extensionality, or axiom of extension, is one of the axioms of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory. It says that sets having the same elements ...
: Two sets are the same if they have the same elements. : If and are in and they have the same elements in , then by 's transitivity, they have the same elements (in ). So they are equal (in and thus in ). *
Axiom of empty set In axiomatic set theory, the axiom of empty set is a statement that asserts the existence of a set with no elements. It is an axiom of Kripke–Platek set theory and the variant of general set theory that Burgess (2005) calls "ST," and a demonstra ...
: is a set. : = = ∈ . So ∈ . Since the element relation is the same and no new elements were added, this is the empty set of . * Axiom of pairing: If , are sets, then is a set. : If ∈ and ∈ , then there is some ordinal such that ∈ and ∈. Then = ∈ . Thus ∈ and it has the same meaning for as for . *
Axiom of union In axiomatic set theory, the axiom of union is one of the axioms of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory. This axiom was introduced by Ernst Zermelo. The axiom states that for each set ''x'' there is a set ''y'' whose elements are precisely the elemen ...
: For any set there is a set whose elements are precisely the elements of the elements of . : If ∈ , then its elements are in and their elements are also in . So is a subset of . = ∈ . Thus ∈ . *
Axiom of infinity In axiomatic set theory and the branches of mathematics and philosophy that use it, the axiom of infinity is one of the axioms of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory. It guarantees the existence of at least one infinite set, namely a set containing th ...
: There exists a set such that is in and whenever is in , so is the union y \cup \. : From
transfinite induction Transfinite induction is an extension of mathematical induction to well-ordered sets, for example to sets of ordinal numbers or cardinal numbers. Its correctness is a theorem of ZFC. Induction by cases Let P(\alpha) be a property defined for ...
, we get that each ordinal ∈ . In particular, ∈ and thus ∈ . *
Axiom of separation In many popular versions of axiomatic set theory, the axiom schema of specification, also known as the axiom schema of separation, subset axiom scheme or axiom schema of restricted comprehension is an axiom schema. Essentially, it says that any ...
: Given any set and any proposition (,,...,), is a set. : By induction on subformulas of , one can show that there is an such that contains and ,..., and ( is true in if and only if is true in (this is called the " reflection principle")). So = ∈ . Thus the subset is in . *
Axiom of replacement In set theory, the axiom schema of replacement is a schema of axioms in Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory (ZF) that asserts that the image of any set under any definable mapping is also a set. It is necessary for the construction of certain infinite ...
: Given any set and any mapping (formally defined as a proposition (,) where (,) and P(,) implies = ), is a set. : Let (,) be the formula that relativizes to , i.e. all quantifiers in are restricted to . is a much more complex formula than , but it is still a finite formula, and since was a mapping over , must be a mapping over ; thus we can apply replacement in to . So = is a set in and a subclass of . Again using the axiom of replacement in , we can show that there must be an such that this set is a subset of ∈ . Then one can use the axiom of separation in to finish showing that it is an element of . *
Axiom of power set In mathematics, the axiom of power set is one of the Zermelo–Fraenkel axioms of axiomatic set theory. In the formal language of the Zermelo–Fraenkel axioms, the axiom reads: :\forall x \, \exists y \, \forall z \, \in y \iff \forall w \ ...
: For any set there exists a set , such that the elements of are precisely the subsets of . : In general, some subsets of a set in will not be in . So the whole power set of a set in will usually not be in . What we need here is to show that the intersection of the power set with ''is'' in . Use replacement in to show that there is an α such that the intersection is a subset of . Then the intersection is ∈ . Thus the required set is in . *
Axiom of choice In mathematics, the axiom of choice, or AC, is an axiom of set theory equivalent to the statement that ''a Cartesian product of a collection of non-empty sets is non-empty''. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection ...
: Given a set of mutually disjoint nonempty sets, there is a set (a choice set for ) containing exactly one element from each member of . : One can show that there is a definable well-ordering of which definition works the same way in itself. So one chooses the least element of each member of to form using the axioms of union and separation in . Notice that the proof that is a model of ZFC only requires that be a model of ZF, i.e. we do ''not'' assume that the axiom of choice holds in .


is absolute and minimal

If is any standard model of ZF sharing the same ordinals as , then the defined in is the same as the defined in . In particular, is the same in and , for any ordinal . And the same formulas and parameters in produce the same constructible sets in . Furthermore, since is a subclass of and, similarly, is a subclass of , is the smallest class containing all the ordinals that is a standard model of ZF. Indeed, is the intersection of all such classes. If there is a ''set'' in that is a standard model of ZF, and the ordinal is the set of ordinals that occur in , then is the of . If there is a set that is a standard model of ZF, then the smallest such set is such a . This set is called the minimal model of ZFC. Using the downward Löwenheim–Skolem theorem, one can show that the minimal model (if it exists) is a countable set. Of course, any consistent theory must have a model, so even within the minimal model of set theory there are sets that are models of ZF (assuming ZF is consistent). However, those set models are non-standard. In particular, they do not use the normal element relation and they are not well founded. Because both the of and the of are the real and both the of and the of are the real , we get that is true in and in any that is a model of ZF. However, does not hold in any other standard model of ZF.


and large cardinals

Since , properties of ordinals that depend on the absence of a function or other structure (i.e. Π formulas) are preserved when going down from to . Hence
initial ordinal In a written or published work, an initial capital, also referred to as a drop capital or simply an initial cap, initial, initcapital, initcap or init or a drop cap or drop, is a letter at the beginning of a word, a chapter, or a paragraph that ...
s of cardinals remain initial in . Regular ordinals remain regular in . Weak
limit cardinal In mathematics, limit cardinals are certain cardinal numbers. A cardinal number ''λ'' is a weak limit cardinal if ''λ'' is neither a successor cardinal nor zero. This means that one cannot "reach" ''λ'' from another cardinal by repeated succes ...
s become strong limit cardinals in because the
generalized continuum hypothesis In mathematics, the continuum hypothesis (abbreviated CH) is a hypothesis about the possible sizes of infinite sets. It states that or equivalently, that In Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice (ZFC), this is equivalent to ...
holds in . Weakly
inaccessible cardinal In set theory, an uncountable cardinal is inaccessible if it cannot be obtained from smaller cardinals by the usual operations of cardinal arithmetic. More precisely, a cardinal is strongly inaccessible if it is uncountable, it is not a sum of ...
s become strongly inaccessible. Weakly Mahlo cardinals become strongly Mahlo. And more generally, any large cardinal property weaker than 0 (see the list of large cardinal properties) will be retained in . However, 0 is false in even if true in . So all the large cardinals whose existence implies 0 cease to have those large cardinal properties, but retain the properties weaker than 0 which they also possess. For example,
measurable cardinal In mathematics, a measurable cardinal is a certain kind of large cardinal number. In order to define the concept, one introduces a two-valued measure on a cardinal , or more generally on any set. For a cardinal , it can be described as a subdivisi ...
s cease to be measurable but remain Mahlo in . If 0 holds in , then there is a closed unbounded class of ordinals that are indiscernible in . While some of these are not even initial ordinals in , they have all the large cardinal properties weaker than 0 in . Furthermore, any strictly increasing class function from the class of indiscernibles to itself can be extended in a unique way to an
elementary embedding In model theory, a branch of mathematical logic, two structures ''M'' and ''N'' of the same signature ''σ'' are called elementarily equivalent if they satisfy the same first-order ''σ''-sentences. If ''N'' is a substructure of ''M'', one often ...
of into . This gives a nice structure of repeating segments.


can be well-ordered

There are various ways of well-ordering . Some of these involve the "fine structure" of , which was first described by Ronald Bjorn Jensen in his 1972 paper entitled "The fine structure of the constructible hierarchy". Instead of explaining the fine structure, we will give an outline of how could be well-ordered using only the definition given above. Suppose and are two different sets in and we wish to determine whether or . If first appears in and first appears in and is different from , then let if and only if . Henceforth, we suppose that . The stage uses formulas with parameters from to define the sets and . If one discounts (for the moment) the parameters, the formulas can be given a standard Gödel numbering by the natural numbers. If is the formula with the smallest Gödel number that can be used to define , and is the formula with the smallest Gödel number that can be used to define , and is different from , then let if and only if in the Gödel numbering. Henceforth, we suppose that . Suppose that uses parameters from . Suppose is the sequence of parameters that can be used with to define , and does the same for . Then let if and only if either or ( and ) or ( and and ) etc. This is called the reverse lexicographic ordering; if there are multiple sequences of parameters that define one of the sets, we choose the least one under this ordering. It being understood that each parameter's possible values are ordered according to the restriction of the ordering of to , so this definition involves transfinite recursion on . The well-ordering of the values of single parameters is provided by the inductive hypothesis of the transfinite induction. The values of -tuples of parameters are well-ordered by the product ordering. The formulas with parameters are well-ordered by the ordered sum (by Gödel numbers) of well-orderings. And is well-ordered by the ordered sum (indexed by ) of the orderings on . Notice that this well-ordering can be defined within itself by a formula of set theory with no parameters, only the free-variables and . And this formula gives the same
truth value In logic and mathematics, a truth value, sometimes called a logical value, is a value indicating the relation of a proposition to truth, which in classical logic has only two possible values ('' true'' or '' false''). Computing In some pro ...
regardless of whether it is evaluated in , , or (some other standard model of ZF with the same ordinals) and we will suppose that the formula is false if either or is not in . It is well known that the axiom of choice is equivalent to the ability to well-order every set. Being able to well-order the proper class (as we have done here with ) is equivalent to the
axiom of global choice In mathematics, specifically in class theories, the axiom of global choice is a stronger variant of the axiom of choice that applies to proper classes of sets as well as sets of sets. Informally it states that one can simultaneously choose an ele ...
, which is more powerful than the ordinary
axiom of choice In mathematics, the axiom of choice, or AC, is an axiom of set theory equivalent to the statement that ''a Cartesian product of a collection of non-empty sets is non-empty''. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection ...
because it also covers proper classes of non-empty sets.


has a reflection principle

Proving that the
axiom of separation In many popular versions of axiomatic set theory, the axiom schema of specification, also known as the axiom schema of separation, subset axiom scheme or axiom schema of restricted comprehension is an axiom schema. Essentially, it says that any ...
,
axiom of replacement In set theory, the axiom schema of replacement is a schema of axioms in Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory (ZF) that asserts that the image of any set under any definable mapping is also a set. It is necessary for the construction of certain infinite ...
, and
axiom of choice In mathematics, the axiom of choice, or AC, is an axiom of set theory equivalent to the statement that ''a Cartesian product of a collection of non-empty sets is non-empty''. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection ...
hold in requires (at least as shown above) the use of a reflection principle for . Here we describe such a principle. By induction on < , we can use ZF in to prove that for any ordinal , there is an ordinal > such that for any sentence (,...,) with ,..., in and containing fewer than symbols (counting a constant symbol for an element of as one symbol) we get that (,...,) holds in if and only if it holds in .


The generalized continuum hypothesis holds in

Let S \in L_\alpha , and let be any constructible subset of . Then there is some with T \in L_, so for some formula and some z_i drawn from L_\beta. By the downward Löwenheim–Skolem theorem and
Mostowski collapse In mathematical logic, the Mostowski collapse lemma, also known as the Shepherdson–Mostowski collapse, is a theorem of set theory introduced by and . Statement Suppose that ''R'' is a binary relation on a class ''X'' such that *''R'' is s ...
, there must be some transitive set containing L_\alpha and some w_i, and having the same first-order theory as L_\beta with the w_i substituted for the z_i; and this will have the same cardinal as L_\alpha. Since V = L is true in L_\beta, it is also true in , so K = L_\gamma for some having the same cardinal as . And T = \ = \ because L_\beta and L_\gamma have the same theory. So is in fact in L_. So all the constructible subsets of an infinite set have ranks with (at most) the same cardinal as the rank of ; it follows that if is the initial ordinal for , then L \cap \mathcal(S) \subseteq L_\delta serves as the "power set" of within . Thus this "power set" L \cap \mathcal(S) \in L_. And this in turn means that the "power set" of has cardinal at most , , , , . Assuming itself has cardinal , the "power set" must then have cardinal exactly . But this is precisely the
generalized continuum hypothesis In mathematics, the continuum hypothesis (abbreviated CH) is a hypothesis about the possible sizes of infinite sets. It states that or equivalently, that In Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice (ZFC), this is equivalent to ...
relativized to .


Constructible sets are definable from the ordinals

There is a formula of set theory that expresses the idea that = . It has only free variables for and . Using this we can expand the definition of each constructible set. If ∈ , then = for some formula and some ,..., in . This is equivalent to saying that: for all , ∈ if and only if here exists such that = and ∈ and (,,,...,)where (,...) is the result of restricting each quantifier in (...) to . Notice that each ∈ for some < . Combine formulas for the 's with the formula for and apply existential quantifiers over the 's outside and one gets a formula that defines the constructible set using only the ordinals that appear in expressions like = as parameters. Example: The set is constructible. It is the unique set that satisfies the formula: where Ord (a) is short for: Actually, even this complex formula has been simplified from what the instructions given in the first paragraph would yield. But the point remains, there is a formula of set theory that is true only for the desired constructible set and that contains parameters only for ordinals.


Relative constructibility

Sometimes it is desirable to find a model of set theory that is narrow like , but that includes or is influenced by a set that is not constructible. This gives rise to the concept of relative constructibility, of which there are two flavors, denoted by () and []. The class () for a non-constructible set is the intersection of all classes that are standard models of set theory and contain and all the ordinals. () is defined by
transfinite recursion Transfinite induction is an extension of mathematical induction to well-ordered sets, for example to sets of ordinal numbers or cardinal numbers. Its correctness is a theorem of ZFC. Induction by cases Let P(\alpha) be a property defined for a ...
as follows: *() = the smallest transitive set containing as an element, i.e. the
transitive closure In mathematics, the transitive closure of a binary relation on a set is the smallest relation on that contains and is transitive. For finite sets, "smallest" can be taken in its usual sense, of having the fewest related pairs; for infinite ...
of . *() = Def (()) *If is a limit ordinal, then L_(A) = \bigcup_ L_(A) \! . *L(A) = \bigcup_ L_(A) \! . If () contains a well-ordering of the transitive closure of , then this can be extended to a well-ordering of (). Otherwise, the axiom of choice will fail in (). A common example is L(\mathbb), the smallest model that contains all the real numbers, which is used extensively in modern descriptive set theory. The class [] is the class of sets whose construction is influenced by , where may be a (presumably non-constructible) set or a proper class. The definition of this class uses Def (), which is the same as Def () except instead of evaluating the truth of formulas in the model (,∈), one uses the model (,∈,) where is a unary predicate. The intended interpretation of () is ∈ . Then the definition of [] is exactly that of only with Def replaced by Def. [] is always a model of the axiom of choice. Even if is a set, is not necessarily itself a member of [], although it always is if is a set of ordinals. The sets in () or [] are usually not actually constructible, and the properties of these models may be quite different from the properties of itself.


See also

* Axiom of constructibility * Statements true in L * Reflection principle * Axiomatic set theory *
Transitive set In set theory, a branch of mathematics, a set A is called transitive if either of the following equivalent conditions hold: * whenever x \in A, and y \in x, then y \in A. * whenever x \in A, and x is not an urelement, then x is a subset of A. Simil ...
*
L(R) In set theory, L(R) (pronounced L of R) is the smallest transitive inner model of ZF containing all the ordinals and all the reals. Construction It can be constructed in a manner analogous to the construction of L (that is, Gödel's constructi ...
* Ordinal definable


Notes


References

* * * * * * {{DEFAULTSORT:Constructible Universe Works by Kurt Gödel